Monday 29 September 2014

Thinking Functionally 1: Education

Moving on with my book, this is the sketch for Chapter 4. Chapters 4 and 5 deal with two aspects of functionalism: here I deal with functionalism in educational thinking - both in the managerialist sense and also in what I call the 'deep functionalism' of cybernetics. In Chapter 6 I will deal with functionalism in the thinking about information. Still lots to do, and hopefully no clangers! (although the good thing about blogging this stuff is that I'm more likely to iron out problems...)

Introduction: Functionalism and the Question of Efficient Education

Educational institutions are complex. They comprise departments for academic disciplines, research, marketing, libraries, estates management, IT deployment, finance and so on. To see each of these performing a function, with a particular purpose lies at the root of functionalism. Functionalism sees that the architecture of the enterprise of education may always be improved, in the same way that the architecture of a business might be improved: efficiencies can be introduced, often with the help of new technology. Whether using Taylorist scientific management, analysing the workflows of academics, or even through introducing wholesale Fordist reorganisation of educational processes, optimised and efficient delivery of education has been a driver both for well-intentioned educational reorganisation (to reduce costs to learners) or for (arguably) ill-intentioned managerial intervention with the goal of maximising profits. Here we must ask, Can education be 'efficient'? What does efficiency in education mean?

In terms of inspecting its efficiency, a common topic of debate is the expense of education and how it should be paid for. In this debate, typically we see arguments about efficiency combined with arguments about fairness. The reasons for this lie in the fact that it is impossible to discuss efficiency in education in isolation from both macro and micro-economic mechanisms which will bear upon the constitution of society in the wake of education, and on the rights and obligations of individuals subject to education. For example, we can ask, If Higher Education is funded by everyone (through taxes), and not everyone attends university, is it efficient, irrespective of it being fair? To what extent does the answer to that question depend on how the money is used within the institution? To what extent does it depend on what education gives society? The institution of education might appear to be grossly inefficient and an expensive drain on the taxpayer, but to reform it would change its nature, and with it the nature of society: how might the efficiency of higher education be measured against the benefits to the whole of society in such a model? If, alternatively, education is funded by only those who attend, the burden of funding on the individual is much greater than it would be if it was funded by everyone. Is this more efficient? What are the knock-on effects on society? If (to take a popular solution to this problem) education is funded on the basis of loans which are taken out and repaid by those who attend, but who only repay if they earn enough to afford later in life, is this more efficient? And what happens to the money within the institution? If Vice-Chancellors award themselves huge pay rises (as they have done in recent years) is this a mark of efficiency (as VCs usually claim!)? If VCs have led cost-cutting initiatives which have squashed academic salaries, introduced institutional fear and compromised academic freedom, can this be defended as being 'efficient'? The problem is that whilst efficiencies might be sought by identifying the functions of components of education, the function of education itself is contested. 

Functionalist thinking can work at many levels. I will make a simple distinction between 'shallow functionalism' and ‘deep functionalism’. Shallow functionalism is the thinking about the functions of the components of the institution of education, the way that those components inter-operate, and so on. This is the Taylorist agenda in education. Deep functionalism looks at similar problems with a greater degree of granularity: what are the components of learning processes, what are the components of teaching, of the curriculum, of knowledge itself. Thinking relating to deep functionalism belongs to the discipline of cybernetics. The relationship between deep functionalism and shallow functionalism presents new questions about how we thinking about 'solving the problem' of education, how we think about 'identifying the problem of education'.

Shallow functionalism

The shallow functional problem begins with the way that institutions and society is organised. We might draw this as a simple hierarchical diagram with government and education ministers at the top and teachers and students at the bottom. In between are various organisational units: schools, universities, colleges, each of which has a head who is responsible for coordinating the provision of courses, resources, teachers and timetables. Teachers themselves have the responsibility for coordinating the activities of their learners, making sure national standards (like exams) are met satisfactorily, and the expectations of learners (and, in schools, their parents) are satisfied.

The hierarchy here is clear. Each individual has a function. Within the contemporary University, there are particular functions which are identified as for 'quality', 'validation', 'assessment', 'certification', and so on. Each of these units performs a function ascribed to them within the structure. Such functions are determined at different levels of the structure. For example, the reason why we have 'validation' as an activity in the University is so as to ensure that the things students are taught fit into a general and comparable schema of 'subjects for which degrees might be awarded' within the national sector of universities. Validation is a function emerging as a knock-on effect of other functions within the university system. The individual responsible for 'validation' in the university is the person who has to fill in forms, attend meetings, review documentation and feed the results of this to the institutional hierarchy.

Similarly, the assessment boards within the university have a function to verify the marks awarded by teachers to their students. Typically marks for modules are presented to the group of staff concerned, and discussions ensue as to what decisions should be taken in each case. This panel is seen as fundamentally important in guaranteeing the award of degrees to individuals. What if it didn't happen? What if anyone could award anyone else a degree? Then the system as an education system becomes incoherent: the end result is a perceived injustice on the part of some learners who find their efforts unfavourably viewed purely because of bad luck or lack of transparent organisation.

The functional differentiation within the education system has evolved over time.  From origins in the individualistic practices of apprenticeship learning, the monastery and so on, preferred hierarchical models arose which privileged the fairness and equity and stability of an education system. The advocates of change in the education system are those who see that this evolutionary process is incomplete; that further evolution is required in order to ensure that the functions performed by the different components of the education, and the functions performed by individuals within those units are all optimal, and that therefore the function of the education system as a whole is tightly and efficiently specified.

However, there remain a number of problems with this picture. Whilst the hierarchy of functions specify the arrangements of documents passing between departments which assure quality, fairness, and so on, there are no 'real' people. Institutions do not contain functionaries; they contain real persons, with real histories, real hang-ups, real talents, and so on. Everybody concerned is involved in a process of problem-solving: the question within institutions is whose problems count for the most; who gets to pursue a solution to their problem, and who else loses as a result? Institutions constitute themselves with real politics.

The actual 'evolutionary' processes which determine the functions of the institution rely on various arguments which present the latest problem solution in an “ethical” light - it is the 'right' thing to do. Such statements are usually made by those in power. Functional determination is not a process of natural selection because any selection is determined by power not by any inherent natural property within each individual: the dominant species in any institution dwarfs the power of everyone else.  This process becomes more marked when powerful individuals arm themselves with new technologies. It has been argued that technologies are often used as tools for the class struggle, but this is more often the way in which senior managers might enhance their power over everyone else. The ethical arguments for such change amount to declarations of status of new instruments of engagement.

It is for this reason that functionalist thinking has become associated with managerialist doctrine. That the seeking of efficiencies of the system frequently costs the jobs of many of the workers. It is in fighting this naive view that deep functionalism is sometimes invoked as a way of challenging the managerial hierarchy - either by re-determining the functions of education so that institutional structures are no longer needed (for example the recent experiments with MOOCs), or by highlighting the deep processes of individual learning and drawing attention to the epistemological gulf between functionalist philosophies of management and the processes of learning and growth of culture which they threaten.

A hierarchy of function is a kind of model. The boxes in a model indicate departments and people. The lines delineate 'information flows'. Those are the communication channels between people. For thinking about is meant by information in this context, I will address this in the next chapter. But typically in institutions, the information flows contain reports and formal communications which are the result of some process which has been executed by the unit concerned; their necessity has usually been determined by higher-order power functions. Failure to produce reports will be deemed to be “not working”, and the workers within the unit will probably be sacked.

If EdTech has been a tragic enterprise over the last 10 years then it has been because it hoped to establish itself with the ambition and ideals of deep functionalism, only (in the end) to have strengthened the hand of shallow functionalists. In understanding the reasons for this, we now have to turn to the background behind the deep functionalism that started it all. Here we have to consider a different kind of model.

Deep Functionalism and Educational Technology

Deep functionalist models consider the arrangement of components of individual behaviour, communication, self-organisation and consciousness. The principle feature of deep functionalist thinking is not just a greater granularity in the determination of components, but increasing complexity in the interrelationship of those components: in particular, the relationship of circular inter-connectedness. Circular inter-connectedness, or feedback, was one of the principal features of psychological and biological models and early functional models date to before the 19th century. Piaget's model of perturbation and adaptation in organisms provides the classic early example of this kind of deep functionalism. But the thinking about deep functionalism goes back further to the origins of the discipline which concerned the interaction of components at a deep level, and in particular, the circular relationships between the action of different components which produce behaviours which can appear chaotic or life-like.

Piaget's mechanism is one of feedback between components, and it was this model which was one of the founding principles behind the pedagogical models which informed thinking about learning and teaching. Among the most influential work within educational technology is that of Gordon Pask, whose conversation theory attempted to identify the functional components of communication within the teaching and learning context. This model was simplified in the late 1990s by Diana Laurillard as her 'conversation model', which subsequently was used as one of the bases of constructivist pedagogy.

However, just as the shallow functionalist models failed to work, or at least relied on power relations in order to work, so the deep functionalist models and the technologies that they have inspired have also often failed to work. In a passage in Diana Laurillard’s book on “Learning as a Design Science”, she states the problem:
“The promise of learning technologies is that they appear to provide what the theorists are calling for. Because they are interactive, communicative, user-controlled technologies, they fit well with the requirement for social-constructivist, active learning. They have had little critique from educational design theorists. On the other hand, the empirical work on what is actually happening in education now that technology is widespread has shown that the reality falls far short of the promise."
She then goes on to cite various studies which indicate causes for this 'falling short'. These include Larry Cuban's study which pointed to:
·       Teachers have too little time to find and evaluate software
·       They do not have appropriate training and development opportunities
·       It is too soon – we need decades to learn how to use new technology
·       Educational institutions are organized around traditional practices

She goes on to echo these findings by stating:
"While we cannot expect that a revolution in the quality and effectiveness of education will necessarily result from the wider use of technology, we should expect the education system to be able to discover how to exploit its potential more effectively. It has to be teachers and lecturers who lead the way on this. No-one else can do it. But they need much more support than they are getting."

However, here we see a common feature of functionalism, both shallow and deep: functionalist theories struggle to inspect themselves. The odd thing in Laurillard’s analysis is that at no point is it suggested that the theories might be wrong. The finger points at the agency of teachers and learners and the structural circumstances within which they operate. In other words, deep functionalism is used to attack shallow functionalism.

Most interventions in education are situated against a background of theory, and it is often with this theoretical background that researchers situate themselves. Given the difficulties of empirical verification in any social science, the relationship between these descriptions is metaphorical at best, and such models are often a poor match for real experience. The difficulty in adapting these abstractions presents an interesting question about the relationship between theories, researchers, practitioners and the academic community. That the personal identity of researchers becomes associated with the validation of a particular analytical perspective or a theoretical proposition. Either it is a theoretical proposition which is to be defended or a particular method of research, which itself will be situated against a theoretical proposition (which often lies latent). To critique theory is not just an intellectual demand to articulate new theory (which is difficult enough), but it is also to question the theoretical assumptions that often form the basis for professional and personal identities of the researcher. On top of this, critique of school or college structures  (which are often blamed for implementation failures) provides a more ready-to-hand target for critique rather than theoretical deficiency.

This is a question about the nature of functionalist thought as a precursor to any theoretical abstraction and technological inervention. What is the relationship between analytical thought and its categories to the real world of experiences and events? For Hume, whose thinking was fundamental in the establishment of scientific method, there was no possible direct access to real causation: causation was a mental construct created by scientists in the light of regular successions of observed events. The models of education present an interesting case of Humean causal theory because there are no regular successions of observed events: events are (at most) partially regular; only in the physical sciences are event regularities possible. Given that merely partial regularities are observable, what are the conditions for the construction of educational theories? The answer to this is the use of modelling and isomorphism between models and reality: educational science has proceeded as a process of generating, modelling and inspecting metaphors of real processes.

Functionalism and the Model

When Laurillard discusses the extant ‘theoretical models’ (Dewey, Vygotsky, Piaget) she presents a variety of theories of learning. She attempts to subsume these models within her own ‘conversational model’ which she derived from the work of Gordon Pask. She defends the fact that these models of learning haven’t changed by arguing that “learning doesn’t change”. How should we read this? Does it mean that Dewey, Vygotsky and Piaget were right? Or does it mean that “there is no need to change the theoretical foundations of our educational design, irrespective of whether the interventions work or not”. Basically, there is an assumption that the model which has served as a foundation for design of educational interventions isn’t broken because it served its purpose in being a model for the design of educational interventions, irrespective of its ability to provide a way of predicting the likely results of educational interventions.

Such deficiencies in modelling are not uncommon in the social sciences. In economics, for example, econometric models which fail to explain and (certainly) to predict the events of economic life continue to appear in economic journal papers. The deficiencies of the model appear to serve a process of endless critique of policy as attempts are made to make policy interventions fit the prescribed models. This continues to the point where it is difficult to publish a paper in an economics journal which does not contain an econometric formula. Yet, the principal figures of economics (Keynes, Hayek, etc) used very little mathematics, and Hayek in particular was scathing in the emerging fashion for econometrics.

A similar situation of adherence to formalisations as the basis for theory has emerged in education. In education, this takes the form of slavish adherence to established theoretical models to underpin practice: a tendency which might be called ‘modellism’. Models are associated with ideological positions in education. The dominance of constructivist thinking, which (as we said in chapter 1) is grounded in solid and reasonable pedagogical experience – is nevertheless a foundation for models of reality which (partly because of their affinity to pedagogical practice) are hard to critique, lest those who hold to them feel that their most cherished values about education are under attack. In trying to address this situation, we need to understand the nature of these models.

Laurillard hopes her ‘conversation model’ provides a generalisation of the available theories of e-learnning. She states that she would have liked to have made a simpler model, but she feels that simple model (like Kolb’s learning cycles, or double-loop learning) leave out too much. That she is able to produce a model which is commensurable with these existing models owes partly to the fact that each of the models she identifies have a shared provenance in the discipline of cybernetics.

The Machinic Allegory of the Cybernetic Model

Cybernetics is a discipline of model building, and particularly understanding the properties of systems with circularity in their connections. Cybernetics is difficult to describe. Its efforts at defining itself (multiple definitions abound) testify to the fact that it doesn’t have the same kind of constitution as other established sciences, cybernetics grew from a period of interdisciplinary creativity and science that emerged from the Word War II, it was recognised that there was the possibility of making connections between ‘feedback and control’ within the newly discovered mechanical devices of the war (in cybernetics case, it was the missile detection systems which Norbert Wiener had been developing in MIT), and the biological mechanisms of living things. It appears as a kind of playful philosophising, where physical or logical mechanical creations with unusual properties are explored, and the questions raised are used to speculate on the nature of the world. Pickering calls this ‘ontological theatre’: a kind of allegorical process of exploring fundamental mechanisms and relating them to reality. Cybernetics provides an alternative to philosophy as a means of description of the world. With emphasis on feedback and indeterminacy, cybernetics brought with it its own mathematics which provided the ground for deeper investigations which, ultimately were to produce many spin-offs which now have their own separate disciplines (and rarely acknowledge their shared heritage) including Computer Science, Artificial Intelligence, Family Therapy, Management Science, biology. Self-organising systems became the principal metaphor behind these systems and generic models could be provided which could cover a range of different phenomena.

Machines with circular connections exhibit behaviour which becomes unpredictable in ways in that can make a machine appear to have ‘life’. One of the first machines with this property was developed by psychiatrist Ross Ashby. His ‘homeostat’ was a machine which contained four oscillating mechanisms whose output values were wired into the inputs of other oscillators. When activated, the different gauges oscillate in apparently random patterns, a change in each individual motor prompting reactions in each of the others. By making the machine and observing the behaviour, the possibility of making distinctions about the behaviour about the machine becomes possible. At the same time, it also becomes possible to consider the nature of this 'model' and its relationship to the natural world. The distinctions surrounding the homeostat provided the opportunity to introduce new concepts: attenuation, amplification. These distinctions feature in a new kind of 'allegory' about social life and psychological phenomena like learning. The homeostat creates events in which understanding is a performative process of engagement: cybernetic machines and models 'tell stories' about the phenomena of consciousness and understanding. Cybernetics is a new kind of metaphysical allegory to account for the way things come to be, and for the way things might become.

The latter emphasis on becoming pinpoints the evolutionary hopes contained within cybernetic understanding. There are many similarities between evolutionary explanation and cybernetic understanding: indeed, for those scientists who have sought to develop Darwinian evolutionary theory, cybernetics has been a powerful tool which they have used to dig deeper into the components of the emergence of life. As with evolutionary explanation, the central feature in these kinds of explanations is time. It was initially in the mathematics of time-series that Wiener first articulated the cybernetic dynamics as an example of irreversibility: each state depended on some prior state, and differences of initial conditions could produce dramatically different patterns of behaviour (a physical manifestation of the point made by Poincaré many years earlier). Given the dependence on states on previous states, and the irreversibility of the processes of emergence, there needed to be a way of thinking about the connection between the variation in states and the conditions under which states varied.

Just as evolutionary explanation regards selection and probability as its principle mechanical drivers over time, cybernetics takes as its principal driver the inter-relationships between components each of which can occupy a finite number of states at any particular moment. Ashby noticed that the number of possible states in a component at any point in time was related to the number of states in other components. In suggesting counting the number of possible states at any one point, he called his measure of the number of possible states of a machine Variety, and stated his axiom that the variety of a system can only be absorbed by the variety of another system. In other words, equilibrium between components depended on the balancing of the number of possible states in each component. An imbalance caused fluctuations in behaviour and uncertainty. The technique of counting variety, and Ashby’s associated law has many everyday applications: in the classroom, the teacher has the variety of a single human being; whilst the class has the variety of 30 human beings. Somehow, the teacher has to manage this variety, which they do by attenuating the variety in the class (with rules and regulations), and amplifying their own variety (with a central position where they can be seen, and a chalk-board).

Ashby’s Law represents deep functionalism's alternative to evolutionary language: instead of genes competing for supremacy, complex organisms interact in ways which preserve their own internal variety management across their different components. Given the new kind of language of deep functionalism and cybernetics, the predominant concerns of shallow functionalism can be re-inspected. What does the organisation hierarchy look like if instead of identifying the components of the organisation as those which perform the functions of marketing, sales, accounts and so on, we examine the way that variety is managed from the macro to the micro level? What does the enterprise of the educational institution look like as a multi-level variety-management operation? What impact do technologies have in helping to manage variety through either attenuation or amplification? Most importantly, by this route, might it be possible to characterise the more basic qualities of mind and establish better ways of organising newly re-described components of education to provide a more enlightening way of organising education?

Of the pioneers of cybernetics who asked the questions about the organisation, Stafford Beer applied Ashby’s principles to re-describe the organisation chart of the institution. Beer’s approach was to allegorize fundamental components he considered to be vital to the successful management of variety in any organisation, and indeed in any organism. Beer’s Viable System Model led him to Chile where he was invited to rewire the Chilean economy under Salvadore Allende. Using Telex machines and a rudimentary 1972 computer, a control centre was established which had feeds of production information from the entire Chilean economy. Decisions could be taken in the light of information received. In the history of cybernetics, there is perhaps no more spectacular example of the aspiration of deep functionalism.

Beer’s work characterises the power and ambition of deep functionalist thinking for re-describing social institutions and transforming them, at the level of individual consciousness and experience, the same principles were used to address psycho-social pathologies emerging from human communication and experience. American anthropologist Margaret Mead was one of the first scientists present at Macy conferences, but she was later joined by her husband Gregory Bateson who saw in the descriptions of ‘feedback’ dynamics within trans-cultural, and trans-species systems a way of describing human pathology which if apprehended could avert the ecological catastrophe that many cyberneticians (including Heinz von Foerster) were already predicting. Bateson’s thinking about system dynamics goes back to Ashby in recognising the fundamental distinction as that of the ‘difference’. Differences are perturbations to a system’s equilibrium, and differences cause change in a system: Bateson argues that what human’s consider to be ‘information’ is “a difference that makes a difference that…” The dynamics of difference-making result in differences occurring at different ‘levels’ in an organism. Influenced by Russell and Whitehead’s class-set theory, Bateson defines different classes of difference. Consciousness involves the interaction of different difference-processing mechanisms. In examining the learning processes of children as they grow into adults, he observed that basic mechanism of stimulus and response at one level, gave way to deeper levels of coordination as higher-level differences concern not basic stimuli, but the results of accommodation to primary responses to stimuli. Tertiary levels of response occur in response to those differences produced by secondary levels: the response to the adaptation processes to the primary response. There are two important phenomena which arise from this mechanism: on the one hand, there is, for Bateson, emergent consciousness which arises through the interaction of different levels of description in a system. Secondly, there is emergent pathology: different levels of description may contradict each other – particularly in inter-human communication. It is in these different levels of description that Bateson becomes particularly interested.

One particular situation is what he called the ‘double-bind’: a situation where one level of description conflicts with another in a contradictory way, where a third level of control prohibits either party in being able to “see” the situation they are caught in. In the double-bind Bateson saw the political relationship between masters and slaves, the dynamics of war, addiction or depression. In the dynamics of emergent levels of organisation, Bateson saw the processes of learning from basic experience of stimulus and response, to higher order functions of sciences and the arts. [more to do]

Pask’s Conversation Theory and Teaching Machines

Whilst Bateson’s project was one of radical redescription, with interventions occurring across a range of phenomena (from dolphins to psychotherapy), Gordon Pask used a similar approach to experiment directly with new technologies for learning. As with all cyberneticians, Pask’s interests were very varied: his contributions range from educational technology, art, architecture, biological computing to epistemological concerns around the nature of concepts and understanding.  It encompassed the connection between self-organising systems, constructivist epistemology and a theory of society. However, Pask is perhaps most important as one of the founders of experimentation with teaching machines. It was with these machinces that Pask explored his interest in communication and the ways individuals learn and adapt from one another and the ways that they acquire concepts about the world, which they then communicate.

Displaying a circularity typical of cyberneticians, Pask’s work in education revolved around the concept of the “concept”: what is a concept and how are they related to communication and learning? Pask’s theory of concepts has many similarities to von Foerster’s theory of object. For Pask, the concept is a stabilised pattern of interactions between individuals and the world. Pask’s approach is a kind of meta-epistemology, which regards concepts as both ideal and subjective – since they are realised in individual minds – whilst exhibiting the properties of objectivity  in the eddies of stability in the interations between people in the world. In order to realise his theory of concepts, Pask requires two things: he requires a mechanism that drives the process of conceptualising. And then he requires a “field” which bounds the operation of this mechanism and allows for the formation of concepts and the interactions between people. Pask calls these two aspects simply an M-machine and a P-machine. An M-machine is the hardware – biological substrate, and in the case of human beings, the brain. The P-machine is the software – some kind of storage for emerging concepts. Importantly, the P-machine may exist within a single M-machine, or across many M-machines. In the latter case, one may talk of social groups, shared discourses and (most importantly) shared concepts between members of social groups. Pask sees as a process of maintaining stable conceptual forms as a broader process of maintaining individual identity. Luhmann sees individual identities as being constituted out of the self-organising dynamics of communications; Pask posits an ultimately individualistic and psychological mechanism of maintaining conceptual structures in an interactionist context.
This kind of deep functionalism presents difficult questions: How are concepts communicated? It is this part of his theory which Laurillard is drawn to, and whilst his explanation stands on its own at one level, the extent to which its assumptions draw on his much more convoluted assertions about the nature of concepts is a sign of particular problems further along the road. Fundamentally, conceptual structures are realised through processes of communication. In teaching and learning processes, teachers attempt to coordinate their understanding of conceptual structures with learners’ understandings by making interventions in contexts, and encouraging learners to articulate their understandings through a process Pask calls “teach-back”. Through repeated exchanges, activities (which are different kinds of context) and exercises, teachers and learners gradually harmonise their conceptual formulations.

So from the shallow functionalism of units of organisation of the university to the deep functionalism of concepts, communication and psychology, how do these things interact? Pask built his conversation theory into a theory of society. Within his work is situated the adaptation-assimilation mechanisms of Piaget, the social constructivist theory of Vygotsky, the situated cognition of Lave and Wenger, and many other theories. The breadth of this work provides the ground for Laurillard’s ambition to embrace the other models that she admires, and indeed, within Pask’s model, there is some commensurability between the cybernetic provenance of Senge, Kolb, Piaget, and others.

From Deep Functionalism to Epistemology and Critique

Whilst cybernetics relation to philosophy is somewhat strained (Luhmann humorously characterises the relationship with philosophers turning up at the cyberneticians party like the uninvited “angry fairy”) the deep functionalism of cybernetics must eventually end up in philosophical territory: for all the speculation about the nature of the world, cybernetics struggles to be anything other than metaphysical. Its identification of processes of variety management, difference and extrapolating these to the processes of consciousness attest to a particular view on knowledge and being in the world. Having said this, cybernetics asks the question as to the nature of reality in a new way: with the demonstrable dynamics of machines and the logic of its ideas and its mathematics, cybernetics presents a model of the metaphysical realm which appears more coherent than those presented by philosophers from past ages. Such a view was clearly held by Bateson who called cybernetics “the biggest bite from the tree of knowledge man has taken for 2000 years”, and his epistemology focused on the importance of language and communication as a dynamic process of difference-making which resulted in the co-creation of reality. By this logic, empiricist views of ‘the real’, the ‘observable’ and so on were challenged: reality was a construct. It’s an irony that the philosopher who would most closely agree with this position is David Hume, who was similarly sceptical about reality, but whose work established the foundations for modern empirical method.

The central difficulty that Bateson addressed was the problem of observation. A philosophical shift was signalled by Margaret Mead, who wrote in 1968 of the need for “cybernetics of cybernetics”. Mead’s plea for a cybernetics which turns its focus on cybernetics itself was seen to focus immediately on the work by two Chilean biologists, Humberto Maturana and Francisco Varela.
Maturana and Varela’s work on cellular organisation appeared to demonstrate (down the microscope), that cells were self-organising, self-reproducing entities. The question then became, if cells are like this, what about language? What about human relations? What about objectivity? Maturana carried this work forwards in arguing that media of transmission were in fact fictions – the results of self-organising processes. There was no information, there was no language: there were processes of languaging between biological entities. That there was an empirical biological basis behind Maturana’s epistemology introduced the seeds of a problem with reality: his work could be characterised as a ‘biological reductionism’. However, it wasn’t just biology that was pointing in this direction. Shortly after Maturana and Varela’s intervention, Heinz von Foerster argued for a mathematical orientation towards 2nd order cybernetics. In considering the nature of objects and the objection to radical idealism that was first proposed by Dr. Johnson, Von Foerster worked on a way in which the identification of objects could be explained through the patterning of sensory information, where stable patterns of interaction could be determined irrespective of the point of view. He called these points of stability of interaction ‘eigenvalues’ and his work subsequently was expanded by other cybernetic mathematicians, notably the topologist Louis Kauffman.

Maturana and Varela’s ideas had a further impact, and one which Maturana (in particular) objected to. This was the idea that communications themselves could be self-organising. Niklass Luhmann’s view of the world was based on 2nd order cybernetics, yet his approach was essentially an inversion of Maturana’s biological emphasis. Luhmann suggested that it was communications, not biological entities, which should be seen to be self-organising. Biological entities became then the means by which communications were reproduced and transformed in society. This move enabled Luhmann to redescribe the phenomena of the social sciences from the perspective of self-reproducing systems. More importantly, it meant Luhmann could engage in a full-blooded redescription of the major themes in sociology, which resulted in a critical engagement that brought Luhmann’s cybernetics far greater inter-disciplinary attention than anyone else, building as it did on the highly influential social functionalism of Talcott Parsons.

Luhmann’s exclusion of agency is at once challenging and powerful. Luhmann asks whether agency is merely the interaction of communication dynamics. Is meaning simply the calculation of aniticpations of double-contingency of communication? What then matters? What of love? What of passion? Luhmann’s presents powerful answers to these question in “love as passion”, where love is seen as an inter-penetration of psychic systems. Luhmann generally makes 2nd order cyberneticians uncomfortable. Yet his message isn’t radically different from that of Pask’s social theory. Yet Luhmann, more clearly that any other figure in cybernetics , relates the sociological discourse to the cybernetics, but more importantly he reveals the direct inheritance of German idealism, and particular of Kant. It is for this reason that his argument with Jurgen Habermas, who represents a fundamentally different tradition of thinking, is most interesting. However, the revealing of the Kantian inheritance and its problems is where the novelty and magic of cybernetic ‘deep functionalist’ thought can be situated in a deeper tradition of thought.

Deep Functionalism and the Kantian Inheritance

Kant’s importance in the history of philosophy rests on his rejection of a model of the world where meaning lay inherent in nature, not in man. In his enterprise he echoed Hume’s view that causes were not inherent in the natural world, but instead the result of discourse between scientists who contrived reproducible experiments. He made a distinction between analytic knowledge (knowledge is that which can be known inherent to a proposition, as in mathematics) and synthetic knowledge (knowledge constructed in the light of experience). He introduced a new method of philosophical reasoning to ask “given that we can have knowledge of the world in various ways, what must the world be like?” As Von Glasersfeld points out, Kant is not the first to highlight the importance of human construction for coming to know the world (Bentham may have been the first, but Vico also expressed a similar view), but he is the first to devise a completely new philosophical schema within which this might occur. His fundamental question, building on the distinction between the analytic and the synthetic, is how synthetic a priori propositions are possible: how it is that something which is constructed from experience can be known without experience? This was an important question because it concerned the knowledge of God: if synthetic a priori knowledge was impossible, how could God exist? In suggesting an answer, he postulates that human subjectivity must organise perceptions into “categories” of thought. Through the categories Kant was able to justify and analyse the way in which synthetic a priori knowledge and other forms of knowledge were possible. He concluded that knowledge of the world must emerge from human beings, but that human understanding must be constituted in a particular way so as to reach the conclusions about the world with which we are all familiar. This was a metaphysical proposition: the ‘Transcendental subject’ of categorical understanding, which could only be inferred by the way the world was.

In proposing the transcendental subject, Kant made a key assumption: the regularities of the world which Hume had referred to, and which were fundamental to synthetic understanding, was a necessary attribute of the world. This so-called ‘natural necessity’ was itself challenged by Hume, who could see no reason why the world should exhibit regular successions of events if causal mechanisms were human constructs. The transcendental subject was a dual metaphysical assertion: an assertion about the world and an assertion about consciousness. It is this dual assertion upon which Husserl built when devising his phenomenology. 2nd order cybernetics disagrees with Kant on the question of natural necessity. By substituting mechanisms of understanding for Kantian categories, reality is seen through the eyes of the cyberneticians as constituted through interacting communicative processes.

A contrasting approach to Kant is to uphold his view on natural necessity, but to reject his view of the transcendental subject. Bhaskar upholds a different kind of transcendentalism based on the question “Given that science is possible, what must the world be like?” This is to re-ask the Kantian question following Hume with the benefit of hindsight of 200 years of scientific progress. In upholding natural necessity, Bhaskar also rejects not only Hume’s rejection of it, but also rejecting Hume’s assertion that causes are constructs. In arguing instead that causes are real, inherent in the nature of the world, and that science’s job is to discover them (not create them), Bhaskar paints a picture of reality which is very different from the both the cybernetic view, and from Hume’s and Kant’s subjectivist view. The concept of mechanism plays a fundamental in this, with Bhaskar making a key distinction between transitive and intransitive mechanisms: those mechanisms which exist through human agency, and those mechanisms which exist outside human agency. In articulating an argument that welds Aristotelian and Marxist thought with Kantian transcendentalism, Bhaskar argues for a dialectical materialist logic that is fundamentally oriented towards emancipation. From this perspective, the cybernetic view it attacked for not inspecting its ontology: it suffers a linguistic reductionism which excludes causal factors which must, in Bhaskar’s view, be considered if one is to account for reality. The most important of these is absence. Bhaskar’s philosophy suffers similar problems of privileging mechanism that the cybernetic viewpoint is subject to, however, the highlighting of the reductionism to language, and the importance of absence as a cause helps him and other (including Smith) to focus on the concreteness of human experience and the transcendental implications of this on the nature of the world rather than dual transcendentalism of the world (natural necessity) and the subject.

The contrast between these positions presents three critical areas for inspection which form the nexus of the problem space concerning the different varieties of functionalism. On the one hand, there is a critique of actualism from Bhaskar which focuses on the causal power of absence, on the other hand, there is critique of Kant’s correlationism from Meillasoux and Badiou which focuses on whether or not there is natural necessity. This broad area of disagreement then boils down to two concrete issues: the nature of real agency and ethical behaviour, and the nature of real people.

1.       The Correlationist/Actualist Problem

What opens up is a vista on possible ontologies. The differences between positions can be characterised as to the extent to which ontologies assert natural necessity or not (in the language of Meillassoux, whether they are ‘correlationist’ or not) and the extent to which ontologies tend towards a temporal mechanical descriptions which are available to synthetic knowledge and with ‘fit’ as the driving force, as opposed to logical analytic descriptions with truth as the central feature. To identify a range of ontological positions is not to relativise ontology; it is instead to find the resources to situate possible ontologies within a meta-ontological framework.

To begin with, a simple table of the positions under consideration can be constructed:
Nature\subjectivity
Transcendental subjectivity
Concrete subjectivity
Natural necessity
Kantian transcendentalism
Pragmatism

Critical Realism
Natural contingency
2nd-order Cybernetic epistemology

Badiou
Meillisoux

This pinpoints the difference between Kantian ontology and cybernetic otology, so far as the assumptions which are made about the nature of the world. The cybernetic epistemology holds to no particular stance on the nature of reality; there is no natural necessity. However, it still upholds Kant’s transcendental subjectivity, albeit with a mechanistic flavour rather than one of categories. The problem for the the cyberneticians is that their ontology ressupposes time as the fundamental requirement for mechanisms of variety management. Kant’s philosophy, on the other hand, does not describe time-based mechanisms. Having said this, the end-result is the same: what Pask and Luhmann describe is a transcendental subject.

The problem of time is the marker between those approaches which attempt to avoid the transcendentalising of the subject. In Bhaskar, the idea of mechanism plays as important a role in his philosophy as it does in cybernetic thought. The apprehension of mechanism as a concept appears to imply both natural necessity and some degree of subjective transcendentalism: it is natural necessity which determines the regular successions of events which humans can interpret as “mechanistic” through the categories. If there is no natural necessity, as the cyberneticians claim, an alternative to mechanistic description needs to be suggested. Badiou and Meillassoux both argue (in different ways) that reality is essentially contingent: people have bodies and they use languages and the world presents ‘events’ to them. The process of making sense of events, for Badiou, is a process of apprehending truths. In Badiou, mechanism is rejected in favour analytical (i.e. not synthetic) knowledge.

In this actualist/correlationist conflict between possible ontologies, the cybernetic transcendental person fits uncomfortably. Cybernetics rejects natural necessity on the one hand, only to infer it in its embrace of mechanism. This makes its transcendental assertions problematic. The cybernetic subject does not appear to be a real person. Instead, it is a machine which processes communications: in Laurillard’s model, teachers and learners process each others’ communications in the light of engaging with the world. Learners’ descriptions of their learning are used by the teacher to gauge what they might do next. It is hard to see why anything would matter to anyone in this situation. It is hard to see where either a teacher or a learner might become passionate about what they teach. With everything is reduced to language and coordinating mechanisms, why bother with the process at all? Is it possible to have a model of learning without a model of human care which must be its fundamental prerequisite? To understand this, we have to address the question of agency and why things matter to people in the first place.

2.       The problem of action and ethics

Teaching, parenting, caring, empathising and listening are activities carried out because they matter to us. How does cybernetics explain why a person would risk their life to save others? How does it explain why a person would wish to make art or compose music? How does it explain our conscience? Or why people fight each other? In each case, the rational ascription of function to the components of a mechanism (even if it is a conversational mechanism) leads to what Bhaskar calls a ‘flattening-out’ of being: reality becomes a rationally-prescribed mechanical process. What is missing is the acknowledgement of the ‘real’: what it takes to make a ‘real person’.

The causal connection between speech acts of teaching and teach-back with the dynamics of engaging with the context of learning sit within a deeper context which is unspecified. In Bhaskar’s terminology, the correlationism of mechanism to transcendental subjectivity might also be called ‘actualism’ in that they model what either can be actually said to exist (supported with evidence) and suggest mechanisms that are deemed to be actually operating in order to produce the observable effects. Here we see the problem in its essence: learners and teachers have personal histories which will affect the ways in which they interact; much is communicated in ways beyond direct linguistic or bodily utterances; the joy and laughter of learning are absent.

The fact that functionalism tends to box-in real people, whether shallow or deep, problems are encountered when it is intended to coordinate action. Arguments are put forwards as to why such and such should be done, or on warning of the dangers of doing something else. From the historicist rhetoric that much neo-Darwinian thinking inspires, to the deep cybernetic arguments for global ecology, ought is the word that tends to dominate. The issue here concerns another aspect of Hume’s thinking: the fact that he argued that obtaining “oughts” from “is” is something which is impossible.  For Bhaskar, this argument is wrong because Hume’s ontology was wrong. Bhaskar argues that oughts are derivable from is’s: indeed, the emancipatory axiology of his critical realism is precisely determined from navigating the space between is to ought.

What is agency as an ethically-driven process of engaging with the world? Behind any model is a kind of instrumentalisation of the world and instrumentalisation of the engagements between people. The phenomenology of action does not render itself amenable to analytical probing. If agency was to be characterised as ultimately ethical, and that judgements about the rightness of action preceded any action, then a distinction has to be made between the agency of human beings and the agency of any other kind of entity (like a robot). It would also entail a characterisation of ethics which excluded the possibility of an artificial ethic.

The question of agency and models is therefore a question about ethical judgement and action. With regard to ethical judgement, there are a number of ethical positions which philosophers identify as conceptually distinct. The ethical position which might be modellable in some way is the position labelled as ‘consequentialist’: this position considers that agents act through some kind of benefit calculation either to themselves or to the community as a whole. It may be conceivable that a model might be able to characterise a range of calculations of this: von Foerster’s ethical principal “always act to increase the number of possibilities” is an example of a “machine ethic” which would work under these circumstances. However, other ethical positions are less easy to model.

3.       The problem of the person and the new problematisation of the subject

Models are abstract, yet we know life through our constitution as persons. Individual understandings emerge against the backdrop of their own personal experiences, attachments, personal motivations and so on. Kant’s transcendental subject and Pask’s P-machine and Luhmann’s transpersonal communication constructs are united in the absence of real people with these rich dimensions of experience. Modelled agency serve as cyphers of real people – as vague predictors of real behaviour. Yet usually real people are remarkably richer in their response to the world than any model suggests. The failure of econometric calculations about utility functions, agent-based modelling, rational economic behaviour and so on is that they ultimately fail to predict the nature of human agency. All these models are constrained by the variables they consider, and exclude many other variables which in the end are only revealed through practice and experience. The fundamental question that arises from this inability is whether a naturalistic inquiry into the behaviour of individuals is at all possible.
The failings of deep and shallow functionalism in characterising real people ultimately depends on what Smith calls ‘variables sociology’. However carefully the independent variables are chosen for the scientific explaination, the dependent variables appear change according to values other than those defined as ‘independent’. This is the weakness of trying to model individuals as rational agents selecting an action from a set of options. Mechanisms describe what can be actually perceived (by some means or other – even if it is through an agent-based model), but reality extends beyond what can actually be identified to include what isn’t there.

The idea of absence being causal is not restricted to sociology. In cosmology, we popularly understand ‘dark matter’ in the universe as representative of the physical causal forces which must exist for the universe to be consistent. The challenge is to try to find a method whereby absent causes may be unearthed. Bhaskar attributes the identification of concrete absence to the dialectical and methodological process of science itself. This means that a naturalistic inquiry into education is a methodological pursuit with the purpose of determining absences. It is by this absence pursual move that Bhaskar argues that science itself was possible in the first place. In this way, observations are made and mechanisms suggested to explain them, with successful mechanisms being used as a foundation for further investigation and false mechanisms rejected. However, whilst Bhaskar’s position seems deeply sensible, and certainly has formed the foundation for deeper and more sensible thinking about the nature of personhood, what matters to people, and so on, there remain (as we have discussed) problems with the idea of mechanism and the assumption of natural necessity.

Meillassoux’s alternative ontology constrasts with Bhaskar because it doesn’t accept natural necessity as its premise. Meillasoux also begins with Hume, and asks about the conditions under scientists reach conclusions about the nature of the world. Meillasoux’s conclusion is that the Humean practice of constructing causes in the light of event regularities was in fact a processes of determining expectations, or the probabilities of events. However, the probability of anything means that the total number of possible events is calculable. Meillasoux points out that this can’t be the case. This is, in fact, a restatement of Bhaskar’s claim that empirical event regularities are produced under the conditions of closed-system experiments, and that the causal inference could not have been constructed because outside the experimental conditions, many constructed causal mechanisms still hold. Instead of making a transcendental claim on the nature of natural necessity and the ontology of causes (causes are real), Meillasoux appeals for an ontology of truth, arguing that a natural ordering of the world, revealable through mathematics, is at work in the scientist’s specification of the probabilities of events, and that the empirical process amounts to the bringing together of an idealised natural order with an observed natural order. What matters in scientific inquiry is an encounter with ‘events’ of life where the ordering is made explicit. Badiou pinpoints 4 kinds of events: Science itself (and mathematics), art and aesthetic experience, love, and politics and the experience of justice.

Both intellectual moves avoid transcendentalising the person, as is attempted through cybernetics or other kinds of functionalism. Instead it transcendentalises a natural order which can be articulated either through mathematics (Badiou) or through causal mechanisms (Bhaskar). Science proceeds on the basis of positing the natural ordering of things, and engaging in dialogue with the orders of things as revealed through events. Bhaskar’s and Badiou’s positions are related in a number of ways. First, they both articulate the importance of politics as a driver for social emancipation, although Badiou and Meillasoux see other drivers in art, love and science. Secondly the assertion of truth by Meillasoux and Badiou is really the assertion of a dialectical mechanism, similar in force to Bhaskar’s dialectic as an emancipatory force. Finally, Bhaskar’s absences which have a causal power become Badiou’s events themselves: events which are essentially not really there, but through the transformations effected by them reveal aspects of natural order previously undetermined.

Persons have bodies and languages, but they also perceive truth which is revealed to them through events. The weakness of the Paskian model is that it appears that only language is explicitly recognised (although one might suppose that bodies are perhaps implicit in the interactions between the teacher and the learner). Pask will not commit either to truth on the one hand (to satisfy Badiou and Meillasoux), or will commit to natural necessity and a materialist dialectic of emancipation (to satisfy Bhaskar). What emerges is a flat ungrounded model with little explanatory or predictive power, but with some strong and essentially unprovable metaphysical assertions. Is a more naturalistic position possible?

Addressing the Naturalistic Gap in Education

The process of determining the function of components remains fundamental to scientific inquiry. The speculation of causal mechanisms, the guessing and imagining of “what might be going on” are all processes which sit at the heart of all scientific inquiry, alongside the desire to understand what might be going on. The methodological question in education, and in the social sciences in general, is the extent to which the practice of those who study what’s going on in education relate to the processes of those who study the behaviour of sub-atomic particles or the origin of the universe. Different ontological stances present different accounts of these processes. Bhaskar, for example, introduces his distinction between the transitive and the instransitive domain to account for the possibility of creating close-system experiments in the physical sciences, together with the social processes of conjectures and refutations, paradigm shifts and so on which characterise the social dimension of science. Bhaskar’s ‘possibility of naturalism’ rests with an ontological grounding of inquiry in the social sciences which situates social mechanisms of reproduction and transformation of social structures with material causal mechanisms. By this logic, all science – not just social science - is politics; it is the political which sits at the heart of his naturalistic ontology. However, Bhaskar’s ontology, as we have seen, is one which rejects Hume’s scepticism about reality, and upholds natural necessity in the form of the intransitive domain and the reality of causes.

The alternative possibility of naturalism rests with Badiou and Meillasoux who point to an ontology of mathematical truth. The purpose of naturalistic inquiry – whether it be in science, mathematics, art or in the various dimensions of human relations – is to uncover truths relating to the ordering of the world. By this logic, Hume’s scepticism about causes is upheld; his regularity theory of causation is reframed as a statistical theory of human expectation, the nature of the difference between physical experiment and social experiment being one of different orders of expectation whose logic is potentially knowable.

Both these positions articulate a positive vision for the social science. Both demand progressive closure of the gap between theory and practice, openness to refutation of theory, and a fundamental grounding in political reality and the concreteness of persons. Both have methodological processes by which they might achieve their aims. In Bhaskar’s case, perhaps the most widely deployed methodological approach is Pawson and Tilley’s Realistic Evaluation of Minger’s multimethodology. Both these methods are effectively meta-methods which seek critique of different methods for examining what happens, so that not only the results of experiment are examined, but so too are the implicit ontologies lying behind the methods themselves. Both techniques privilege causal mechanisms and tend to avoid the less mechanistic and more subtle aspects of Bhaskar’s later philosophy. In practice, mechanistic descriptions can be hard to reconcile, articulating different processes from different levels of abstraction.

The alternative is a logico-empirical movement which was first suggested by Elster, who combined measurement with the representation of different social theoretical statements using rational choice theory and game theory (before later claiming that rational choice theory was deficient).  Badiou and Meillasoux’s ontology presents an alternative which combines mathematical analysis and measurement. One of the key problems they address is the way in which different social theories may be represented and compared. Taking the view that different social theories are different descriptions of social ordering, Badiou’s utilisation of the mathematics and set and category theory presents the possibility for the representation and evaluation of different social theories.

Whatever the prospects for these different positions, the need for a metatheory about theorising and empirical practice within the social sciences, and particularly education, seems beyond question. There are likely to be many possible metatheories, and there are likely to be a number of different possible ontologies upon which they sit. The space for theoretical development in education is a space of possible world-views – not just views about the nature of education, or the purpose of education – but fundamental different views on what it is to be human, and on the nature of the world. Against this background, the modelling of education through cybernetics or other kinds of functionalism becomes merely a way of creating new kinds of events in the light of which we hope to learn new things. The point about the technologies in education about which Laurillard bemoans the failure is not, and could never have been, implementation. It was illumination.

Conclusion

Functionalism’s dominance in modern culture rests on its unique position as the ‘solution-finding’ paradigm. What I have hoped to articulate here is that functionalism’s solutions are invariably deficient, but that functionalism’s strength lies on the one hand in its ability to coordinate action, and on the other to ask new questions. When we devise new interventions in education, be they pedagogical or technical, we create a new “theatre of events”. What matters is the effect of those events on the practice of people witnessing them. New interventions might be devised in the light of functionalist theories (either deep or shallow), but providing participants are open to ask deeper questions about the world in the light of the events that occur, rejecting or refining theories as they go, then critical scientific advances within education ought to be possible. However, this proviso is a very big one. The reality of human behaviour appears to lead individuals to becoming attached to explanatory theories as a means of articulating explanations and designing interventions which, when they don’t work, cause individuals not to abandon their theories, but instead to assert them more strongly, blaming factors in implementation rather than poor theorising for the situation.

Here we should inquire about the relationship between particular properties of particular theories which lead to uncritical or dogmatic acceptance, and particular properties and tendencies of particular individuals. Do totalising theories attract people who are less likely to let go of them? I have attempted to show how the totalising ambitions of cybernetic description are ungrounded and that whilst cybernetic ideas can raise very powerful questions about ontology, they sit uneasily between philosophical positions which are fundamentally incompatible. It may be that the first step to dealing with over-attachment to totalisations is to unpick the totalisation and highlight the tensions contained within it. However, on its own, this is unlikely to be enough: it is merely a discursive intervention, and suffers the same idealisation of the person as the theories it critiques.

Real people in education have real feelings, real histories, real ambitions, real fears and it is likely to be only through particular circumstances that any progress might be made. The challenge is to ensure the conditions under which authentic interactions between real people can occur in such a way so as to ensure the continual asking of questions about the nature of what we attempt to do in education. Laurillard hints at this in her book: “only real teachers can solve the problems of their students”.


No comments: